Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

учебный год 2023 / Dworkin-Precedent

.pdf
Скачиваний:
2
Добавлен:
19.12.2022
Размер:
495.29 Кб
Скачать

A Note on Dworkin and Precedent Author(s): David Pannick

Source: The Modern Law Review, Vol. 43, No. 1, (Jan., 1980), pp. 36-44 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of the Modern Law Review

Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1095083

Accessed: 01/06/2008 10:30

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

http://www.jstor.org

A NOTE ON DWORKIN AND PRECEDENT

I

A THEORY of adjudication remains one of the more elusive goals of modem jurisprudence. Who should resolve a legal dispute and how should they resolve it? In Taking Rights Seriously,l Ronald Dworkin attacks the positivist thesis of H. L. A. Hart2 that in hard cases judges exercise a quasi-legislative discretion in deciding for one party or the other. Dworkin rejects this as descriptively false. He also finds it normatively unsatisfactory because undemocratic (since it involves lawmaking by judges) and unfair (because those laws are applied ex

post facto to the litigants).

Dworkin's theory of adjudication is that in all cases judges weigh

and apply competing rights. Even in hard cases, one party has a right to win. His theory of adjudication is tied to a theory of what law is. For Dworkin, law embraces moral and political as well as strictly legal rights.3 Dworkin develops a third theory of law. Law is neither merely the rights and duties created by legislation, custom and precedent; nor is law merely the edicts of natural law or morality. Rather, law is the body of rights given expression to in legislation, custom and precedent, plus the political and moral rights that are

implied by the political theory that best explains and justifies the existing legislation, custom and precedent. The task of a super-human judge, Hercules, is to construct a political and moral theory that best explains and justifies the existing legal material, that ruling theory being the best guide to the rights Hercules must apply to reach the correct decision 4 in a hard case. Dworkin has produced a sophisti- cated version of the "Open Sesame " 5 theory of adjudication.

1 Taking Rights Seriously (Duckworth, 1977. New impression with an appendix, "A Reply to Critics," 1978). Henceforth cited as " Dworkin."

2The Concept of Law (Oxford, 1961).

3Dworkin, Introduction p. xii: ". . . individuals may have legal rights other

than those created by explicit decision or practice; that is, they may have rights to specific adjudicative decisions even in hard cases when no explicit decision or practice requires a decision either way."

In deciding hard cases, judges rely on principles as well as rules. Dworkin's contention is that these principles are part of "law," and not something extra-legal which a judge has a discretion when and how to apply. Dworkin therefore redefines

these principles as legal rights.

4 In Dworkin's jurisprudence, to every hard case there is an uniquely correct solution. If judges fail to weigh rights correctly it is not because of any ambiguity

in the question posed and not because of any incompatibility between the rights. There are only practical difficulties: failures to understand the question, defects in

moral reasoning powers. Dworkin has reintroduced into

jurisprudence the

errors

of a monist vision so powerfully and persistently exposed

in other areas of

life by

Isaiah Berlin. Sir Isaiah's writings develop the central theme that values and experi- ence cannot be accommodated within a consistent framework without the loss of

much that is thought valuable. The very notion of harmony and unity denigrates man by denying the heterogeneous quality of human life. This is as powerful a

critique of a legal philosophy as it is of a political philosophy. Hercules

cannot

claim immunity from the paillful dilemmas of choice felt by all other men.

 

5 Lord Reid "The

Judge as Lawmaker," 12 J.S.P.T.L. 22. " There was a time

when it was thought

almost indecent to suggest that judges make law-they

only

36

Jan. 1980] A NOTE ON DWORKIN AND PRECEDENT

37

Dworkin argues that his theory is not defeated by complaints about judicial law-making or retroactivity. Hercules decides hard common

law cases on grounds of principle (weighing rights), not policy. Hence he is not a quasi-legislator, and the principles are not applied ex post facto.6

My concern is with Dworkin's claim that the rights thesis "pro-

vides a more satisfactory explanation of how judges use precedent in hard cases than the explanation provided by any theory that gives a more prominent place to policy." 7 He asserts a link between

principled adjudication and the doctrine of precedent.

"An argument of principle can supply a justification for a particular decision, under the doctrine of responsibility, only if the principle cited can be shown to be consistent with earlier decisions not recanted, and with decisions that the institution is prepared to make in the hypothetical circumstances. That is hardly surprising,but the argument would not hold if judges based their decisions on arguments of policy. They would be free to say that some policy might be adequately served by serving it in the case

at bar, providing, for example, just the right subsidy to some troubled industry, so that neither earlier decisions nor hypo- thetical future decisions need be understood as serving the same

policy." 8

Dworkin explains that the doctrine of precedent gives a judicial decision two types of force. It has enactment force (its effect on future

cases covered by its exact words) and gravitational force (its influence on later cases that fall outside the language of its opinion).9 The language of a judicial decision does not explain its gravitational force. Nor do arguments of reliance, convenience, or accumulated wisdom. Gravitational force is justified by "the fairness of treating like cases alike." 10

Because precedent is based on fairness, a judicial decision has gravitational force only if it was decided on grounds of principle. If an earlier decision is seen as justified by an argument of policy, then it only has enactment force."1

II

The doctrine of precedent is difficult to reconcile with a theory of adjudication based on the entitlement of the litigants to the correct decision (reached by weighing their competing rights). A judge striving

declare it. Those with a taste for fairy tales seem to have thought that in some Aladdin's cave there is hidden the common law in all its splendour and that on a

judge's appointment there descends on him knowledge of the magic words Open Sesame. Bad decisons are given when a judge muddles the pass word and the wrong door opens. But we do not believe in fairy tales any more."

6Dworkin, p. 85.

7Dworkin, p. 87.

S Dworkin, p. 88.

9Dworkin, p. 111.

10Dworkin, p. 113 (and pp. 318-319 in " A Reply to Critics ").

11 Dworkin, p. 113.

(Cited in Goodhart, 50 L.Q.R. 40, 46).

38

THE MODERN LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 43

to reach the right answerin a hard case has no need for rules of precedentobliginghim to give gravitationalor enactmentforce to past decisions.If the judge believesan earlierdecisionwas correct,

he will apply its reasoningand its conclusionto the present case withoutbeing forced to do so by rulesof precedent.He alreadyhas an obligationto reachthe rightdecision.If precedentis to add some- thing to the fundamentalduty of the judge to weigh rights,it can only be a role that challengesthe very roots of the rights thesis. Precedentdemandsthat a judgemustgive considerationto an earlier

decisionnot because he thinks the decisionwas a correctone, but, rather,even thoughhe thinksit was (legally)incorrect.Staredecisis

is

only

of

in so faras it ensures

for authoritiesthat

 

 

importance

respect

would otherwisebe ignored.12Precedent,far from being explained and justifiedby fairness,is opposed to fairness,if fairnessmeans

cases

 

to

rights.

deciding

according

Herculesis, it is true, obligedto developa theoryof mistakesto

enable him to

avoid giving gravitationforce (and, perhaps, also

enactmentforce) to at least some wrong decisions.13It is doubtful whetherhe can avoid givingforce to all wrongdecisions.But, even if he can, he has merely anaesthetisedthe role of precedent;stare decisiswould becomeredundantin the rightsthesis,since that thesis alreadydemandsthat the judge decides each case by weighingand

applyingcompetingrights.

 

for the

of

 

"Fairness" cannotbe the

 

wrong

decisions.'4

 

justification

repetition

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

III

 

 

Can Dworkin

fromthe

that

is redundant

escape

 

 

arguments precedent

 

in the rightsthesis, and that wheneverprecedentis given a role it conflictswith fairness?

We can reject two weak defencesof precedentas fairnessin the rightsthesis.Precedentcould servea secretarialrole,the past decision

being a guide to the presentjudge on how to weigh precedentsand

12 Radin, 33 Columbia Law Review 199. The fact that precedent is redundant if it compels respect only for correct decisions explains the contempt in which precedent is often held.

See Bentham's outburst (in his Constitutional Code, Book 2, Art. 49): precedent "is acting without reason, to the declared exclusion of reason, and thereby in declared opposition to reason"

Similarly, in Shakespeare's The Merchant of Venice (Act IV, Scene I) Portia declares: "'Twill be recorded for a precedent, And many an error by the same example Will rush into the state. It cannot be."

13Dworkin, pp. 119-122.

14Swift (in Gulliver's Travels-" A Voyage to the Houyhnhnms," Chap. 5) explains: " It is a maxim among these lawyers that whatever has been done before may legally be done again, and therefore they take special care to record all the decisions formerly made against common justice and the general reason of mankind.

These, under the name of precedents, they produce as authorities to justify the most iniquitous opinions, and the judges never fail of decreeing accordingly."

However, Joseph Raz, in "Professor Dworkin's Theory of Rights" (1978) 26 Political Studies 123, 135 argues that sometimes there are good reasons to perpetuate

a decision that should not, in the first place, have been made.

Jan. 1980] A NOTE ON DWORKIN AND PRECEDENT

39

statutes.l5The

hereis to

explainwhy

a

 

of entitle-

 

difficulty

 

balancing

ments done 50, 100 or 200 years ago should bind today's judge,

as new statuteshavebeenenacted,and the

rulingpolitical

particularly

theory therebychanged.The second weak justificationargues that the judgein the earliercase was betterqualified,and so morelikely

to develop correctlythe political theory than is the judge in the

case.This

of

as fairness

at best,

only

present

explanation

precedent

is,

 

acceptablewhen the earlierdecisionemanatedfrom a superiorcourt

(and the explanationdoes not allowfor changesin the rulingpolitical theorythat have occurredsince the decisionof the earliercourt).

The only strongdefenceopento Dworkinis to arguethatprecedent is requiredby the rightsthesis,and is basedon fairnessin givingthe litigants their entitlements,because the earlier decision developed the law in some way. Withoutthe earlierdecisionthe law would be

differentin content. The past decisionis thus itself an entitlement, one that judgeswould be in dangerof ignoringbut for the doctrine

of precedent.16

The acceptanceof judicialdecisionsas entitlementsseemsessential

if Dworkinis to allow for the

of the commonlaw. The

 

development

insistencethat the commonlaw evolvescan be termedthe "Galileo"

theory of adjudication.17Without it, Donoghue v. Stevenson 18 would have been similarlydecidedin 1922, 1832or 1632(if an analogycan

be found for

and

glass bottles).

Other

judicial

decisions

 

ginger-beer

 

 

would not influence the correct result in Donoghue v. Stevenson, wheneverlitigated,if thosedecisionsare merelythe correctweighings of existing entitlements.The common law developsbecause wrong judicialdecisions(i.e. ones in which rights are defectivelyweighed) create new rights."

Judicialdecisionsas entitlementsis the best defence of precedent in the rights thesis. However, the foundation of that thesis, and Dworkin'sjustificationof adjudicationas against argumentsfrom

and

is

that

judicial

decisionsare

democracy

retroactivity,

precisely

 

 

15 Cardozo, The

Nature of the Judicial Process (p. 149): "...

'the labour of

judges would be increased almost to the breaking point if every past decision could be re-opened in every case."

16 Dworkin hints at this interpretation. He says, at p. 113: "A precedent is the report of an earlier political decision; the very fact of that decision, as a piece of political history, provides some reason for deciding other cases in a similar way in the future." The earlier decision has a force independent of that possessed by the

rights weighed in it.

17 In Lister v. Romford Ice and Cold Storage Co. [1957] A.C. 555, 591-592, Lord Radcliffe said: "No one really doubts that the common law is a body of law which develops in process of time in response to the development of the society in which it rules. Its movement may not be perceptible at any distinct point in time, nor can we always say how it gets from one point to another; but I do not think

that, for all that, we need abandon the conviction of Galileo that somehow, by some means, there is a movement that takes place."

1s [1932] A.C. 652.

19 We can only avoid the conclusion that judicial decisions are entitlements by arguing that entitlements created by statute have a gravitational force of their own and so affect common law decisions in which they are not directly applied. Statutory entitlements will also cause a change in the ruling political theory.

40

THE MODERN LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 43

not ex post facto legislation. The dilemma is this: if Donoghue v.

Stevenson merely weighed already existing entitlements,it added nothingcreativeto the body of the law, and so no doctrineof precedentis requiredto ensurethat a laterjudgeweighsthose rightsin the sameway; if Donoghuev. Stevensonneedsto be consideredas a precedentbecauseit did add somethingto the law (thatis, if it was an incorrectweighingof entitlements,resultingin a new entitlement),

how do we maintainthe

thesis

from democ-

 

and

 

rights

againstarguments

 

racy

It is true that we do not here have

judicial

 

retroactivity?

 

 

law-makingby discretion.But what we do have is equally anti- pathetic to democracy: a new entitlementis created by a wrong judicial decision.20The only improvementon a theory of judicial discretionis the limitationthe rightsthesisimposeson the procedure by which a judge may createan entitlement.He can only createan entitlementas a by-productof his attempt to reach the correct decisionby weighingexistingentitlementsUndemocratic.law-making is the minimumprice of defendingprecedentin the rightsthesis by seeing judicial decisions as entitlements.21Dworkin concedes that

no judge is Hercules,so mistakeswill be common.If judgesare to make law in hard cases, the objectionsto them consideringmatters of policyseemless persuasive.22

We have, then, a theory that not only do judges reach decisions by applyingexistingrights,but also that a judicialdecisionis itself

an entitlementThis.

of

still cannotbe the basis

 

explanation

precedent

of the enactmentforce of judicial decisions.Even if each judicial decisioncreatesan entitlement,we have no reasonto thinkthat such

an entitlementwill alwaysbe strongenoughto outweighcompeting entitlementsin later cases, and so generatea particulardecisionin the later case when the earlierdecisionis cited as a precedent.Precedent as fairness,with each judicial decisionitself an entitlement, can only explain why judicial decisionsare given considerationin later cases. Judicialdecisionsare merely entitlementsamong other entitlements.This is inadequateto explain enactmentforce, which

20 In The Courts as

Legislators (Holdsworth Club Presidential Lecture, 1964-65),

Lord Diplock said:

"

No lawyer really supposes that such decisions as Rylands v.

Fletcher in the last

century or Donoghue v. Stevenson in this did not change the

law just as much as the Law Reform (Contributory Negligence) Act 1945."

21 Sartorius, "Social

Policy and Judicial Legislation," 1971, 8 Am.Phil.Q. 151,

159-160, argues that because a judge is not perceived as a legislator, and because

he justifies his decisions by reference to pre-existing standards, therefore he is not a legislator even though his decisions change the law. But we know that judges are not perceived as legislators because of the popularity of the doctrine that judges do not make law. Since we are assessing the veracity of that doctrine, its popularity is irrelevant. Judicial reliance on pre-existing standards is relevant in assessing how a judge makes law, but it does not determine whether he is a legislator. If Parliament decided to codify the existing law of contract and, inadvertently, altered the law in the process of codification, this would be as much law-making as if the alterations were deliberate.

22 Wasserstrom, The Judicial Decision (Stanford, 1961), at p. 157 comments: "Once the notion that legal rules are discovered rather than made by the courts is given up, it is difficult to escape the conclusion that these rules ought to be formulated intelligently."

excludea
since no

Jan. 1980] A NOTE ON DWORKIN AND PRECEDENT

41

demandsthat later cases fallingwithinthe exact wordsof the earlier decisionacceptthat earlierdecisionas dispositiveof the presentcase.

IV

The enactmentforce of judicial decisionsis not based on fairness weighing of entitlementsthere occurs. The entitlement createdby the judicial decisionis exclusionaryof all social entitle-

ments(i.e. thosenot createdby judicialdecisionor statute,butderived

indirectlythroughthe ruling political theory that best justifiesthe existingprecedentsand statutes).To explainthe enactmentforce of judicial decisionswe need to recognisejudge-madeentitlementsas

existing

on a

level than social entitlements.

 

higher

Similarlystatutory

entitlements(those directly created by legislation) override other entitlements.23There is little point in these cases in talking of a weighingof entitlementsOne. level of entitlementexcludesthe other.

Ihis is analogousto JosephRaz's explanationof how promisesand other second-orderreasonsare exclusionaryreasonsfor action that weighingof reasonsfor action.24In Dworkin'srightsthesis,

exclusionaryentitlementspreventa weighingof entitlements.

Enactmentforce and

force are creaturesof the same

 

gravitational

species. Enactmentforce is very strong gravitationalforce. As the present case moves furtheraway from the languageof the earlier decision,so the force of thatearlierdecisiondiminishesGravitational.

force, like enactmentforce, excludesconsiderationof social entitle-

ments.25 One can

only

counter

force with the

gravita-

 

 

gravitational

tional force of conflictingdecisions.Enactmentforce goes further.

It excludes considerationof the gravitationalforce of conflicting decisions.There is really little point in talking of the weighingof entitlementsunlesswe mean a conflictbetweengravitationalforces, the clash of enactmentforces, or the battle of social entitlements.

Our effortsto explainthe functionof precedentin the rightsthesis led to the conclusionthat judicial decisionsare themselvesentitle-

ments. This leads to the furtherconclusionthat judge-madeentitle-

mentsare on a higherlevel to socialentitlementsand on a lowerlevel to statutoryentitlements(If. constitutionalentitlementsexist,theywill

occupy an even higher level.) Dworkin commentsthat Herculesis faced with "layers of authority"and a "verticalordering"of legal material.26He may mean,by this, to embracelevels of entitlements.

One problemis that a verticalstructureof entitlementsis difficultto

reconcile with his insistence that "If rights make sense, then the degreesof their importancecannot be so differentthat some count

23 Dworkin bases his political theory on the right to treatment as an equal. It is unclear whether this right can ever be outweighed by judge-made and statutory entitlements, let alone whether it can so easily be excluded by them. The answer may depend on the existence of a higher level of constitutional entitlements.

24Practical Reason and Norms (Hutchinson, 1975).

25It cannot be argued that the strength of gravitational force depends on social entitlements. This would be a circular theory, since social entitlements depend on

the

ruling political theory derived by considering judicial decisions and statutes.

26

Dworkin, p. 117.

42 THE MODERN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 43

not at all when others are mentioned." 27The existence of levels of

entitlements

one tenetof the

thesis: that

adjudication

challenges

rights

concernsthe

 

of entitlements.28

 

 

 

weighing

 

 

 

 

 

V

 

 

 

We have a restatementof Dworkin's

thesis.Dworkinis not

only

 

 

rights

 

describingand justifyingadjudicationby showingit to be basedon a weighingof entitlementsHe. is also developinga theoryof the consequencesof a judicialdecision.A judicialdecisionmust itself be an entitlementif precedentis not to be redundantin the rightsthesis. Judicialdecisionsas entitlementsleads to an objectionfrom demo-

We have the

 

of what

suchentitlementshavein

cracy.

difficulty

weight

withother

whethertherearelevelsof entitle-

comparison

entitlements,

 

ments that exclude a weighingprocess, and whetherfairness can justify the exclusionarynatureof judge-madeentitlements.We also have to explainhow a judgecan dismissan earlierdecisionas a mistake, and so deny it force, if it is an entitlementIf. judicialdecisions are entitlements,how do we explainthe powerof the House of Lords to overruleits own decisions?In the contextof the overrulingpower we do see a weighingof entitlements,judge-madeand social.Yet it is preciselyin this contextof a trueweighingof entitlementsthatprece- dent is ignored.Precedentis not neededto ensurethat entitlements are weighed.Indeed,the force of precedentwould preventany such weighingprocessfrom occurring:the House of Lordswouldmerely followthe earlierdecision.

Dworkin postulatesonly an impure rights thesis, with levels of entitlements.A pure rightsthesis (one whereinall entitlementsare

weighed) would recognisethat statutoryentitlementscould be out- weighedby social entitlements:for example,whenthe rightto treatment as an equal is deniedby a statute.A pure rightsthesis would also cease to ascertainthe rulingpolitical theory that gives us the

contentof our social entitlements

reference

to statutesand

by

solely

 

previousjudicial decisions. If, as Dworkin insists, men have legal

rights other than those expresslycreated by legislationand prior judicialdecisions,why is the contentof that body of rightsso rigidly dependenton the contentof earlierlegislationand adjudication?

The answer is that a pure rights thesis would pose insuperable practicaldifficulties.First, grantedthat men possesslegal rightsthat are not stated in statutesor the subject of express recognitionin

decisionsin earliercases,how areindividual

and

judicial

right-holders

judgesto decidethe weightandcontentof thoserights?Secondly,if a

27Dworkin, pp. 203-204.

28The distinctions between social, judge-made and statutory entitlements are

emphasised by Dworkin's method of ascertaining the ruling political theory (the use of which enables Hercules correctly to identify social entitlements). The body of social rights is evidenced by reference to entitlements on a higher level. Extra-

judicial pronouncements and statements by academics possess no force and are ignored when the ruling political theory is being considered. They occupy a level beneath social entitlements.

Jan. 1980] A NOTE ON DWORKIN AND PRECEDENT

43

judge weighs all legal rights when decidinga case, how are we to ensurethat statutesand judicialdecisionsare effectiveguidesfor the conductof citizensand the decisionsof judges?Dworkin'sanswerto

the firstproblemis to state that the only social rightsrecognisedby law are those evidencedby statutesand judicial decisionsby being thereinimplied.His solutionto the secondproblemis to see judicial decisionsas entitlements,on a higherlevel to social entitlements,but

on a lower level to statutoryentitlements.The solution to each problemis partlyconcretisedin a doctrineof precedent.

It is, then,misleadingto say thatthe doctrineof precedentis based on fairness. Of course, it all depends what we mean by fairness. "Fairness" as the weighingof all entitlementsand the consistent

applicationof principlesfails to capturethe distinctivecontribution of precedentto the rightsthesis.Precedentgives judicialdecisionsan exclusionaryforce that preventsa true weighingof entitlements.It gives to a judicialdecisiona force not presentin the rightsthat were weighedin reachingthe decision.The role of precedentin the rights thesis, apart from reconcilingthe thesis with the evolution of the commonlaw, is to help ensurethat the contentof our legal rightsis not too uncertain,and to help ensurethat the thesis supportsrather than destroysa politicaltheoryof levels of rights.

VI

The discussionso far has, I hope, led to two conclusions.First, that precedenthinders ratherthan ensures a weighingof rights in the

adjudicativeprocess.Secondly,that theremay be, nonetheless,good reasonsfor retainingenactmentandgravitationalforce.Thesereasons have nothingto do with " fairness,"as Dworkindefinesit. They are, I suggest,politicalreasons.

These conclusionsare not wholly surprisingif one stands back from the intricaciesof Dworkin'stheory,and questionsthe intimate connectionhe makesbetweenprincipledadjudicationandthe doctrine

of precedent.Judgescan make perfectlyprincipleddecisionseven if

they are not constrainedto follow earlierdecisions.The principled nature of a decision (whetherit is made by a judge or by anyone else) dependson the presentintentionof the decision-makerto make

the samedecisionin all analogouscasesin the future,anddependson the decisionitself not being generatedby policy considerationsHis.

decision does not become unprincipledmerelybecausehe does not give especial weight to the fact that certain other decisions were decided in a certainway in the past. His presentdecision can be

principledeven thoughhe rejectsthe principlesappliedin the past.

Principle can exist, quite happily, independentof precedent.The crucialpoint is thatthe principleswill be differentin the absenceof a doctrineof precedent:theywillbe moreradical.

Precedentensuresthat the principlesHerculesappliesin hardcases

44

THE MODERN LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 43

are conservative ones.29 It ensures that in searching for solutions to new problems, Hercules must operate with a conservative ideology. He must search the past for authority to justify the principles he wishes to apply. This may be desirable, for example to restrain the reforming instincts of the judge. Or it may be undesirable,causing the stagnation of the common law, its inability to resolve new problems. As Denning L.J. suggested in Packer v. Packer,

"If we never do anything which has not been done before, we shall never get anywhere. The law will stand still whilst the rest of the world goes on; and that will be bad for both." 30

We have to decide whether we want Hercules to be a "timorous

soul" or a "bold spirit." 31 Acceptance or rejection of enactment

and gravitational force in hard cases will be the key to ensuring the success of the choice we make.

Precedent, then, is not essential to principled adjudication in hard cases. Enactment and gravitational force may, indeed, endanger the principled nature of decisions made by Hercules. A judge will find it easier, in hard cases, to shelter behind earlier decisions, rather than articulate and justify the "principles " he is applying to resolve a dispute. Perhaps it was for this reason that Dr. Johnson warned Boswell: "As to precedents, to be sure they will increase in course of time; but the more precedents there are, the less occasion is there for law; that is to say, the less occasion is there for investigating

principles." 32

I am reluctant to commit myself to specifying whether the political justifications for precedent (ensuring conservative principles; enabling the common law to develop, albeit at a slow pace; supporting a political theory of levels of rights; preventing the content of our legal rights from being too uncertain) come under the heading of "principle" or " policy." Dworkin's replies to his critics suggest a degree of caution (or at least a safety-net) when walking that tight-rope. I

merely propose, tentatively, that the political justificationsfor precedent cannot be embraced within the neutral concept of " fairness " used by Dworkin to explain the existence of gravitational force.

DAVID PANNICK.*

29 In "Professor Dworkin's Theory of Rights," 26 Political Studies 123, 133-136, Raz points out that Dworkin's rights thesis is a conservative thesis: "for it instructs [judges] always to perpetuate the existing ideology of the law." Dworkin's rights thesis is, I suggest, a conservative thesis because of the existence of the doctrine of precedent: it is the doctrine of precedent that compels respect for earlier decisions.

30[1953] 2 All E.R. 127, 129.

31The dichotomy suggested by Denning L.J., dissenting, in Candler, v. Crane, Christmas & Co. [1951] 2 K.B. 164, 178.

32

March 28, 1772. Similarly, Cardozo, The Growth of Law (pp. 4-5).

*

B.A., B.C.L., Fellow of All Souls College, Oxford.

Соседние файлы в папке учебный год 2023